Arithmetical hierarchy: If you don't read logic

https://arbital.com/p/1mj

by Eliezer Yudkowsky Jan 17 2016 updated Apr 4 2016


The arithmetical hierarchy is a way of stratifying statements by how many "for every number" and "there exists a number" clauses they contain.

Suppose we say "2 + 1 = 1 + 2". Since this is only a statement about three specific numbers, this statement would occupy the lowest level of the arithmetical hierarchy, which we can equivalently call Δ0, Π0, or Σ0 (the reason for using all three terms will soon become clear).

Next, suppose we say, "For all numbers x: (1 + x) = (x + 1)." This generalizes over all numbers - a universal quantifier - and then makes a statement about each particular number x, that (1 + x) = (x + 1), that involves no further quantifiers and can be verified immediately. This statement is said to be in Π1.

Suppose we say, "There exists a y such that y9=9y." This is a single existential quantifier. To verify it by sheer brute force, we'd need to start from 0 and then consider successive integers y, checking for each particular y whether it was true that y9=9y. Since the statement has a single existential quantifier over y, surrounding a statement that for any particular y is in Δ0, it is said to be in Σ1.

Suppose we say, "For every number x, there exists a prime number y that is greater than x." For any particular c the statement "There is a prime number x that is greater than c" lies in Σ1. Universally quantifying over all c, outside of the Σ1 statement about any particular c, creates a statement in Π2.

Similarly, the statement "There exists a number x such that, for every number y, (x+y)>109 would be in Σ2, since it adjoins a "there exists a number x…" to a statement that lies in Π1 for any particular x.

Generalizing, putting a "There exists an x…" quantifier outside a Πn statement creates a Σn+1 statement, and putting a "For all y" quantifier outside a Σn statement about y creates a Πn+1 statement.

If there are equivalent ways of formulating a sentence such that it can be seen to occupy both Σn and Πn, we say that it belongs to Δn.

Consequences for epistemic reasoning

Statements in Σ1 are verifiable. Taking "There exists y such that y9=9y" as the example, soon as we find any one particular y such that y9=9y, we can verify the central formula y9=9y for that particular y immediately, and then we're done.

Statements in Π1 are falsifiable. We can decisively demonstrate them to be wrong by finding a particular example where the core statement is false.

Sentences in Δ1 are those which are both falsifiable and verifiable in finite time.

Π2 and Σ2 statements are not definitely verifiable or falsifiable by brute force. E.g. for a Π2 statement, "For every x there is a y", even after we've found a y for many particular x, we haven't tested all the x; and even if we've searched some particular x and not yet found any y, we haven't yet searched all possible y. But statements in this class can still be probabilistically supported or countersupported by examples; each time we find an example of a y for another x, we might become a little more confident, and if for some x we fail to find a y after a long time searching, we might become a little less confident.

Subtleties

Bounded quantifiers don't count

The statement, "For every number x, there exists a prime number y smaller than xx" is said to lie in Π1, not Π2. Since the existence statement is bounded by xx, a function which can itself be computed in bounded time, in principle we could just search through every possible y that is less than xx and test it in bounded time. For any particular x, such as x=2, we could indeed replace the statement "There exists a prime number y less than 22" with the statement "Either 0 is a prime number, or 1 is a prime number, or 2 is a prime number, or 3 is a prime number" which contains no quantifiers at all. Thus, in general within the arithmetical hierarchy, bounded quantifiers don't count.

We similarly observe that the statement "For every number x, there exists a prime number y smaller than xx" is falsifiable - we could falsify it by exhibiting some particular constant c, testing all the numbers smaller than cc, and failing to find any primes. (As would in fact be the case if we tested c=1.)

Similar adjacent quantifiers can be collapsed into a single quantifier

Since bounded quantifiers don't count, it follows more subtly that we can combine adjacent quantifiers of the same type, since there are bounded ways to encode multiple numbers in a single number. For example, the numbers x and y can be encoded into a single number z=2x3y. So if I want to say, "For every nonzero integers x, y, and z, it is not the case that x3+y3=z3" I can actually just say, "There's no number w such that there exist nonzero x, y, and z less than w with w=2x3y5z and x3+y3=z3." Thus, the three adjacent universal quantifiers over all x, y, and z can be combined. However, if the sentence is "for all x there exists y", there's no way to translate that into a statement about a single number z, so only alike quantifiers can be collapsed in this way.

With these subtleties in hand, we can see, e.g., that Fermat's Last Theorem belongs in Π1, since FLT says, "For every w greater than 2 and x, y, z greater than 0, it's not the case that xw+yw=zw. This implies that like any other Π1 statement, Fermat's Last Theorem should be falsifiable by brute force but not verifiable by brute force. If a counterexample existed, we could eventually find it by brute force (even if it took longer than the age of the universe) and exhibit that example to decisively disprove FLT; but there's no amount of brute-force verification of particular examples that can prove the larger theorem.

How implications interact with falsifiability and verifiability

In general, if the implication XY holds, then:

The converse implications do not hold.

As an example, consider the Π2 statement "For every prime x, there is a larger prime y". Ignoring the existence of proofs, this statement is unfalsifiable by direct observation. The falsifiable Π1 statement, "For every prime x, there is a larger prime y=f(x)=4x+1 would if true imply the Π2 statement." But this doesn't make the Π2 statement falsifiable. Even if the Π1 assertion about the primeness of 4x+1 in particular is false, the Π2 statement can still be true (as is indeed the case). [comment: Patrick, is there a particular reason we want this knowledge to be accessible to people who don't natively read logic? I.e. were you making something else rely on it?]